Critique of Violence
Walter Benjamin (1927)
The task of a critique of violence can be summarized as that of expounding its relation to law and justice. For a cause, however effective, becomes violent, in the precise sense of the word, only when it bears on moral issues. The sphere of these issues is defined by the concepts of law and justice. With regard to the first of these, "it is clear that the most elementary relationship within any legal system is that of ends to means, and, further, that violence can first be sought only in the realm of means, not of ends. These observations provide a critique of violence with more—and certainly different—premises than perhaps appears. For if violence is a means, a criterion for criticizing it might seem immediately available. It imposes itself in the question whether violence, in a given case, is a means to a just or an unjust end. A critique of it would then be implied in a system of just ends. This, however, is not so. For what such a system, assuming it to be secure against all doubt, would contain is not a criterion for violence itself as a principle, but, rather, the criterion for cases of its use. The question would remain open whether violence, as a principle, could be a moral means even to just ends. To resolve this question a more exact criterion is needed, which would discriminate within the sphere of means themselves, without regard for the ends they serve.
The exclusion of
this more precise critical approach is perhaps the predominant feature
of a main current of legal philosophy: natural law. It perceives in
the use of violent means to just ends no greater problem than a man
sees in his "right" to move his body in the direction of a desired goal.
According to this view (for which the terrorism in the French Revolution
provided an Ideological foundation), violence is a product of nature,
as it were a raw material, the use of which is in no way problematical,
unless ' force is misused for unjust ends. If, according to the theory
of ' state of natural law, people give up all their violence for the
sake of '. the state, this is done on the assumption (which Spinoza,
for example, states explicitly in his Tractatus Theologico-Politicus)
that the individual, before the conclusion of this rational contract,
has de jure the right to use at will the violence that is de facto at
his disposal. Perhaps these views have been recently rekindled by Darwin's
biology, which, in a thoroughly dogmatic manner, regards violence as
the only original means, besides natural selection, appropriate to all
the vital ends of nature. Popular Darwinistic philosophy has often shown
how short a step it is from this dogma of natural history to the still
cruder one of legal philosophy, which holds that the violence that is,
almost alone, appropriate to natural ends is thereby also legal. This
thesis of natural law that regards violence as a natural datum is diametrically
opposed to that of positive law, which sees violence as a product of
history. If natural law can judge all existing law only in criticizing
its ends, so positive law can judge all evolving law only in criticizing
its means. If justice is the criterion of ends, legality is that of
means. Notwithstanding this antithesis, however, both schools meet in
their common basic dogma: just ends can be attained by justified means,
justified means used for just ends. Natural law attempts, by the justness
of the ends, to "justify" the means, positive law to "guarantee" the
justness of the ends through the justification of the means. This antinomy
would prove insoluble if the common dogmatic assumption were false,
if justified means on the one hand and just ends on the other were in
irreconcilable conflict. No insight into this problem could be gained,
however, until the circular argument had been broken, and mutually independent
criteria both of just ends and of justified means were established.